In my last discussion of Lucian’s Alexander, I characterized it as an early instance of a journalistic genre that’s now common enough: the longform treatment/exposure of a con job. People write those articles now for polemic reasons, but mostly because there’s money in it. Nothing makes us feel smarter than seeing a fraud laid bare, and that’s a feeling we’ll pay for. The journalist’s job is to give us that feeling by telling us about all the dopes that fell for a scam which we, thanks to inside information that the journalist herself has helpfully provided, recognize at once for what it is.
We would like to believe we’re that smart. The journalist’s perspective is kind of a prosthetic in this regard, and not only because it gives us the information that keeps us from being fooled. It also provides an apparently objective judgment that the thing in question really is a con, which is a level of certainty we practically never get in daily life, where so many of our friends, acquaintances and coworkers might well be defrauding us in ways we’d never pick up on (or probably acknowledge if someone else dumped the evidence in our laps). That’s the condition of modern capitalism, Mandeville’s Fable of the Bees brought to life: cheat thy neighbor shall be the whole of the law. Journalistic exposures of con men are at least a symptomatic cure for the thoroughgoing paranoia generated by this state of affairs.
For all these reasons, the work of bringing scams to light strikes us as a far more titillating quest after truth than, say, research into the proper taxonomy of earthworms. The truth about long cons is an operative truth: unlike the earthworm family tree, it makes us happier in all sorts of ways. It provides a direct and immediate ego satisfaction.
It occured to me that this couldn’t be the explanation for what Lucian does in Alexander and also in De morte Peregrini. For one thing, the genre just wasn’t a popular one in the ancient world. Where texts reveal the truth about a con, they almost always do so as part of a larger religious polemic; the uncloaking isn’t its own goal, as in Lucian’s work and in its modern successors. For another thing, what it meant to be “intelligent” in the Roman Empire was also a little different from what it means to be “intelligent” nowadays. To be smart meant to know a lot of stuff, much of it marvelous and possibly untrue; that one should have a critical sense about these things always seems to have been a minority position. Finally, people were worried about getting swindled, but not so pervasively as nowadays. Back then, at least, if someone got caught running a scam they’d be punished – not held up as a model capitalist, and certainly not elected president.
This is why, at the beginning of the Alexander, Lucian does something that modern journalists almost never do: he apologizes for the sordid character of his subject matter. “αἰδοῦμαι μὲν οὖν ὑπὲρ ἀμφοῖν,” he says: I’m ashamed of you, Celsus, for asking me to write about this fellow, and of myself, Lucian, for taking your request seriously. Alexander doesn’t so much deserve to be the subject of a learned disquisition as to be torn to pieces in the amphitheatre by apes and foxes.
Yet Alexander attains to a certain majesty of evil just insofar as he’s managed to infest the whole world, not just Asia Minor, with his thefts and his piracies. In this respect, he resembles his famous namesake, Alexander the Great, who conquered the world using more straightforward means some 500 years earlier. Alexander of Abonouteichos merits remembrance as the kind of world-conqueror that it’s possible for a Greek to be under the domination of Rome – as a Greek virus that returns to infect the space of the Empire.
That’s one way of justifying Lucian’s interest in this so discreditable figure. Another, also pursued by Lucian, is to treat Alexander as a monument of shit, an Augean Stables from which Lucian, being no Heracles himself, can only bring out a bucket or two of dung. That’s an early invention of what you might call the sleazy sublime. Alexander doesn’t really need Lucian’s help to be remembered: he’s already a monumental structure on the Greek cultural landscape. Lucian’s interest is only in showing what’s inside.
To be aware of the nature of Lucian’s interest in this project should also, of course, be to read the essay differently. Would we, for instance, have noticed otherwise that Lucian even talks up Alexander’s capacities above our own? What else is the enargeic staging of the snake-god Glykon’s debut (Alexander 15-17) but an account of how we ourselves would probably have been fooled if we’d been exposed to Alexander’s magic without Lucian’s mediation? Even an Epicurus or a Democritus, Lucian coyly concludes, would probably not have been able to see through the scam if he had been standing in the place of Alexander’s Paphlagonian audience.
From this point of view, Lucian is not so much interested in exposing the truth as he is in demonstrating the power of the lie. That the essay still ends up reflecting poorly on Alexander is owing to another set of Lucianic interests entirely, which I’ll discuss in my next post.